I’ve heard from Peter Enns, Ben Witherington, and Roger Olson (do a
google search to find their blogs) how evangelicalism seems to want to hold
onto inerrancy as a dogma (not just doctrine or opinion). To hold it as a dogma is to claim it is
essential, a “must believe” in order to be a properly right-believing (i.e.
orthodox) Christian. It is of the same
status as, for example, the Apostle’s creed.
Yet in actual practice inerrantists kill it
by a thousand qualifications, sometimes resulting in a claim "inerrant in
all it teaches (or taught) in its original autographs." In other words, we get to determine what the inerrant teaching is. We
do that by applying interpretive principles to try to divine the author’s
original intent, or try to divine what God (who is regarded as having inspired
the writing, and is taken by some to be the ultimate author of the text)
intended to teach. And that sort of move,
I can imagine, can be used to defend whatever teaching one wants to dogmatize. For in the end the interpreter often claims
about that interpretation, “this is not what I am saying, this is what God is
saying.” And sometimes, maybe too often,
it gets used as a club to beat others into submission. Such a strategy fuels the Nietzscheans among
us who claim that “truth” is nothing more than power and domination in
disguise. Can't we imagine someone
(maybe they need to have some sort of scholarly credentials) taking some passage that states what strongly
appears to be a falsehood and divining what the original autograph (or God)
might have said or meant such that it (the original) expresses something true
or correct or factual? They have to save
the bible we have from falsehood.
Then, too, it seems they will need to save the Jesus we have from
falsehood. In Mark 2.25-26 Jesus is
recorded as stating that David and his companions took consecrated bread and
ate it, during the time when Abiathar was the high priest. Yet in 1 Samuel 21.1-7, Ahimelech is recorded
as the high priest. Lots of options here
(at least five I can think of), two of which are a) the writer of Mark put a
falsehood into the mouth of Jesus, b) Jesus stated a falsehood and the gospel
writer reports accurately what Jesus said.
Much has been written on it, some of it I find very entertaining.
Rather than having to save the Bible (or Jesus) from error, why not
just hold the view that Jesus stated a falsehood? Does Jesus have to be a know-it-all—not in
the negative sense that that term is often used? Does the doctrine (I think it is a doctrine,
not a dogma) of the sinlessness (the theological term is “impeccability”) of
Jesus entail that he made no mistakes?
Should I think that whenever Jesus was playing the first century
equivalent of baseball, he batted 1.000, never made a fielding error, always
made it home without getting called "out"? Or that when he was learning how to spell, or
do mathematical calculations, he never made a mistake? Or that when he was cutting a board for his
dad, he never forgot to “measure twice, cut once” and never made a wrong cut?
If you are willing to accept that Jesus stated a falsehood, you don’t
have to think that Jesus told a lie (at least not in the Mark 2.25-26
claim). I define a lie as "a) intentionally
communicating what you believe to be a falsehood, b) when the person to whom you
are communicating it expects or deserves what you believe to be the truth, c) in
order to gain some advantage for yourself against that person." Let me give a couple of weird examples; I
state the weird ones to show some of the qualifications in the definition I
gave.
The first example is one in which I knowingly tell a falsehood to gain
an advantage for myself but it is not a lie. Two dozen years ago on a warm
January night, I was in a city park with two friends enjoying 60 degrees in January
and a six-pack of beer. We were breaking
the law by being in the park after dark and by having alcohol in the park. [Side note: I loved it in St. Paul where the
city and county parks had signs posted stating “No alcohol, except beer and
wine.” I guess that is shorter or
clearer than “Alcohol permitted, just not the hard stuff”]. I saw a police car driving into the park by
where my car was parked and where we were standing under the clear but warm
January sky enjoying our conversation and beer.
I told my companions, “put your open beer down, at least six feet away from
you.” Three of the six-pack were
unopened in the carton at my feet. When
the policemen pulled up with their flashlights out, one asked what we were
doing in the park. I responded “enjoying
the beautiful, unusually warm night.” He
asked if we knew the park was closed at night.
I said no. He told us it was a
safety issue, and we shouldn’t be in the park at night for our own safety. He then asked if that beer was ours, and I
said no. He then asked if we’d pick it
up and put it in the trash can nearby. I
said sure, and when I picked up the carton with the unopened three, I said “officer,
these three aren’t opened; is it okay if I put them in my trunk?” He responded “sure.”
Now, according to my definition, did I
lie? I say no; I intentionally said what
was false but not a lie. How so? The officer believed that we were not
trouble-makers. If I had responded
truthfully, he might have had to issue a ticket, or even arrest us. That would have created a lot of work he did
not what to do, taking time that would be better spent on other matters of
public safety. He did not expect the
truth; indeed he did not want the truth.
He wanted us to get our stuff and leave the park. According to my definition, no lie.
The second example is fictional, in which I tell the truth but in doing
so I tell what counts on my definition as a lie. Suppose that on September 11, 2001 at my 10
am class I want to see if I can get the students to want to cancel the class
because I was lazy and hadn’t prepared well.
So I make up a story, saying that just before I left my office I saw on
an internet news site that some planes just crashed into some buildings in New
York, killing all passengers. One of the
buildings has collapsed, and the other is expected to. This is a horrible disaster. The news report said that this is believed to
have been carried out by terrorists, that we should be on the alert, especially
if we are in a building with a large number of people. The students panic, they want to get
out. Class ends. I chuckle to myself that they bought my
story.
In this case, while the truth was
told, it was a lie. How so? I intentionally communicated what I believed to
have been a falsehood (it was, coincidentally true, unbeknownst to me) to
people who expected what I believed to be the truth, and I did so in order to
gain an advantage for myself against them.
Given my definition of a lie, I don’t see Jesus as telling a lie in
Mark 2.25-26. He tells a falsehood
probably believing it is true, but he isn’t doing so in order to gain any
advantage over others. It wouldn’t shock me if Jesus told a lie or
two sometime during his life. It would
shock me if he hadn’t lied a few times as a child. It is similar to my claim that the impeccability
of Christ does not require that in the first century version of basketball he
never missed any shot he took. Even I
could beat Jesus in arm wrestling. I
think I can believe that without having to accept some version of an Arian view
that Jesus was a mere human who became the Son of God at the baptism by John
the Baptizer, symbolized by the Spirit like a dove descending on him (after
which, on this theory, he would have been incapable of lying, even if still
capable of being beat at arm wrestling).
An inerrantist might accept that Jesus stated a falsehood (but no lie),
and still maintain the inerrancy of Mark 2.25-26 by claiming that it is
inerrant in what it teaches. The
inerrantist then has to employ interpretive principles to claim that the intent
of the passage is not to teach about David, or about who the high priest was at
some specific point in history. The
intent is to teach about some deeper significance of the Sabbath. To me, that version of inerrancy does sound
like a death by a thousand qualifications. Furthermore, I can get that interpretation (that
Jesus is teaching something about what the Sabbath is for) without having to
accept inerrancy. And at that point, why
not just give up on inerrancy?
Why not? Because it is a
boundary marker. It marks where all
members of one's theological club stand, thinking only they have orthodoxy on their
side, with anyone not in the inerrantist club standing on the errant, almost
certainly heretical, heterodox side. It
is, in my view, inflating an opinion, or perhaps a doctrine, into a dogma.
No comments:
Post a Comment